In the Name of
Allah
Islam, and Thin / Thick Human Rights
Seyed Sadegh Haghighat[1]
This article deals with the relationship between religion
in general meaning (and Islam in the narrower one) and thin and thick human
rights. Being enriched enough, the literature of “thin and thick” was developed
by most communitarians. A thin morality is one constituted by general and
universal principles, though, a thick morality is that which is constituted by
deliberation conditioned by history, tradition, and culture. As Michael Walzer
suggests, this dualism is an internal feature of every morality.[2] He agrees to an extent with universalism, though
in the sympathy with the opposite principle, he does not prescribe democracy
for all spaces and times.[3] Sissela
Bok makes a similar point: “Certain basic values necessary to collective
survival have had to be formulated in every society. A minimalist [that is,
thin] set of such values can be recognized across societal and other
boundaries.”[4] These
basic values pertain to rights, duties, and norms in three areas: (1) Positive
duties of mutual care and support, (2) negative duties (e.g. no harm to others),
and (3) norms of rudimentary fairness and procedural justice. Bok maintains
that they are necessary for the kind of trust that underlies all social
relations and thus are essential for societal order on all levels. Societies
have produced a diversity of maximalist (thick) values that are not common but
can be consistent with the three kinds of universal minimalist values.
For MacIntyre, sentiments inspire thick religious interpretations of morality contends that any attempt to establish a universal ethic grounded in human nature per se fails to appreciate that there is no universal morality, but that in fact we live in a fragmented world of many moralities.[5]
To understand what Benjamin Gregg means by thin normativity, it would help to understand what he means by the idea that thick normativity characterizes the level of commitment to a creed, an idea, or way of life, which is so strong as to exclude other creeds, ideas, and ways of life. By contrast, thin normativity adheres more or less only to the principle that people should be free to choose. As Gregg notes, thin normativity is inclusive. However, precisely because of its exclusivity, thick normativity simply cannot serve as the basis of a modern society. He respects thick normativities in sub-communities.[6]
Both thick human rights
here and in communitarianism criticize thin liberal human rights. Nevertheless,
thick human rights in this article depart from the communitarian ones in their
source. Whereas communitarians stress tradition and religion as the cultural, I
use them here as the religious too. Religion for modernists, including
communitarians, is not considered as transcendental, however, religion here has
two levels: the very holy texts (religion 1), and the interpretations of them
(religion 2). Arguing about the relationship between religion and human rights
means religion 1 & 2, not the cultural implications of religion.
Given that there may be
some kind of contradiction between religion and human rights based on humanism,
there is no necessity to demonstrate the compatibility and coordination of
religion (Islam) and Human Rights Declaration. In fact, human rights, here, is
the general meaning of them, and not necessarily what is mentioned in the
Declaration and the two Conventions. For example, Islam and Judaism do not
consider equal rights for believers/unbelievers or for men/women. Hence, human
rights, here, overlap with the Declaration and the Conventions. While
communitarians try to enrich liberal human rights by culture and tradition, it
is attempted in this article to picture the possibility of enriching human
rights (in general meaning) by religion. Although religion is considered as a
pre-modern concept, and hence can not categorically compared with modern human
rights, it has the capacity to be assessed with regard to the criteria of
modern concepts like human rights. In The Distribution of Power in Shiite Political
Thought, I have assessed the capacity of “Shiite political thought” with
regard to the criteria of “distribution of power” as a modern concept.[7] As a
matter of fact, although Muslims in the Prophet’s era did not think about
concepts like human rights, these modern concepts were considered as unthought,
not unthinkable.
Anyway, what is meant
by “thin human rights” is the minimal and liberal ones, and by “thick human
rights” the maximal and religious ones. Whereas thin human rights are general and
universal, the thick ones here, are based on religious bases. Since thin human
rights are based on thin moralities, they need tradition and revelation to be
enriched. Human rights are the rights of human beings as they are human beings,
though, they can be discovered by human reason (to be thin human rights), or by
Divine wisdom (to be thick human rights). Assuming “religious human rights” as
possible and non-paradoxical, this article aims to coordinate between two
levels of human rights: thin human rights as the regulator of the relations
amongst different groups of people in and between countries as a realistic policy,
and thick human rights for the believers as an idealistic guideline. The
point is that Islamic governments and their people need both of these levels to
act with secularists and unbelievers practically, and to think and propagate
their system idealistically. To demonstrate this hypothesis, one needs first to
prove the possibility of enriching human rights, second to show that “religious
human rights” are not paradoxical, third to have a look at the readings of
religion (Islam), and finally to compare thin and thick human rights reasoning.
Possibility
of Enriching Human Rights
With respect to the possibility of enriching thin human rights it seems sufficient to look at the communitarian criticism on liberal human rights. In his book After Virtue[8], MacIntyre illustrates that the Aristotelian tradition can be restated in a way that restores rationality and intelligibility to the moral and social attitudes and commitments. In Whose Justice? Which Rationality?[9], he attempts to show both what makes it rational to act in one way rather than another and what makes it rational to advance and defend one conception of practical rationality rather than another. In this, he compares Aristotle’s conception of justice (based on city-state and phronesis) with that of Aquinas (concerning the compatibility of religious and secular elements) and also with Hume (on the relationship of reasoning to action with the priority of human rationality over religion). His central preoccupation is the nature of the connection between justice and (religious) laws. According to Augustine, justice is what was ordered in The Ten Commandments.[10] Observing that liberalism itself has transformed into a tradition, he sees those conceptions of universality and impersonality to be too thin and meager to supply what is needed. Although his analysis is considered as contextualistic, he tries to get rid of relativism and historicism.[11]
The main communitarian comments on liberalism are: the
politics of community, the conception of “self”, priority of public good over
individual right, considering communities based on here and now, particularism
versus universalism, criticism of liberal neutrality and its claim to be
value-free.[12] As
Oliver Leaman puts it: “Religion fits in with communitarian accounts of
morality, in the sense that it identifies morality with a particular set of
beliefs and practices which are part of community. What makes morality morality
is its accordance with faith, since only God is able to say what morality is.
According to Liberalism, the concepts of public, others, external, communal,
general, universal, religion, emotional, nature, Shari’a, prayer, virtue and religion
are in order constructed out of those of private, self, internal, individual,
particular, personal, philosophy, rational, culture, nomos, awe, wisdom and
rationality.”[13]
Whatever the soundness of liberal principles, the fact remains that many communitarians seem worried by a perception that traditional liberal institutions and practices have contributed to, or at least do not seem up to the task of dealing with, such modern phenomena as alienation from the political process, unbridled greed, loneliness, urban crime, and high divorce rates.
Communitarian
thinkers in the 1980s such as Michael Sandel and Charles Taylor argued that
Rawlsian liberalism rests on an overly individualistic conception of the self.
Whereas Rawls argues that we have a supreme interest in shaping, pursuing, and
revising our own life-plans, he neglects the fact that our selves tend to be
defined or constituted by various communal attachments (e.g., ties to the
family or to a religious tradition) so close to us that they can only be set
aside at great cost, if at all. In an influential essay titled ‘Atomism’,
Charles Taylor objected to the liberal view that ‘men are self-sufficient
outside of society’. Instead,
Whereas Rawls seemed to present his theory of justice as universally true (at least for Euro-American societies), communitarians argued that the standards of justice must be found in forms of life and traditions of particular societies and hence can vary from context to context. Alasdair MacIntyre and Charles Taylor argued that moral and political judgments will depend on the language of reasons and the interpretive framework within which agents view their world. Hence it makes no sense to begin the political enterprise by abstracting oneself from the interpretive dimensions of human beliefs, practices, and institutions. In line with the arguments of ‘1980s communitarians’ such as Michael Walzer, it is argued that justifications for particular practices valued by Western-style liberal democrats should not be made by relying on the abstract and unhistorical universalism that often disables Western liberal democrats. Rather, they should be made from the inside, from specific examples and argumentative strategies that one uses in everyday moral and political debate.[16]
In short, communitarians would enrich thin liberal human
rights by invoking communities of place, or communities based on geographical
location, communities of memory, or groups of strangers who share a
morally-significant history, and psychological communities, or communities of
face-to-face personal interaction governed by sentiments of trust,
co-operation, and altruism. In next part of this article, I want to illustrate
that another item would be possible: communities of religion.
“Religious”
Human Rights
Whether religion (Islam) has an essence in itself or is based
on anti-essentialism, we can talk about the possibility of enriching thin human
rights. In philosophy,
essentialism is the view, that, for any specific kind of entity it is at least
theoretically possible for there to be a set of characteristics all of which
any entity of the specific kind cannot fail to have. This view is contrasted
with non-essentialism which states that for any
given kind of entity there are no specific traits which entities of that kind
must have. An essence characterizes a substance
or a form,
in the sense of the Forms or Ideas in Platonic
idealism. It is permanent, unalterable, and eternal; and present in
every possible world. Classical humanism has an essentialist conception of the human being,
which means that it believes in an eternal and unchangeable human nature.
This viewpoint has been criticized by Marx, Nietzsche,
and Sartre
and many modern and existential thinkers. Plato is considered as an
essentialist because he believed in ideal forms of which every object is just a
poor copy. Since ideas are eternal in his view, they are superior to material
objects. When we see objects in the material world, we understand them through
their relationships between them. This belief is clearly manifested in his
famous parable of the cave. Karl Popper
splits the ambiguous term realism into essentialism and realism.
He uses essentialism whenever he means the opposite of nominalism,
and realism
only as opposed to idealism. Essentialism in ethics is claiming that some things
are wrong in an absolute sense, for example murder breaks a universal,
objective and natural moral law and not merely an adventitious, socially or
ethically constructed one. Essentialist positions on gender, race, or other
group characteristics, consider these to be fixed traits, while not allowing
for variations among individuals or over time. Contemporary proponents of identity politics
including feminism,
and anti-racist activists generally take constructionist viewpoints, agreeing with Simone de Beauvoir that "one is not born,
but becomes a woman", for example. Essentialism is used by some historians
in listing essential cultural characteristics of a particular nation or
culture. A people can be understood in this way. Opposed to this model of
interpretation are historical studies which turn from essences to focus on the
particular circumstances of time and place.[17]
All traditional
readings of religion believe in essentialism, however, historical,
phenomenological and hermeneutical readings are based on anti-essentialism.
Considering religion as a historical or a phenomenological case implies
rejecting any kind of essence for it; since it would be dedicated to special
space and time. Whereas there is no essence for modern concepts like democracy
and liberty, traditionalists regard religion with its essence. According to
them, anti-essentialism leads to reducing religions to their context, and implies
rejecting the teachings of a religion. Nevertheless, as we will see here, when
religion in the view of essentialists can come together with human rights (to
have “religious human rights”) the case would be easier if we do not consider
any essence for religion; since it will, therefore, have no essence to be
regarded as a barrier to being mixed with human rights. Reason and revelation
are two main sources of human rights as the rights of human beings because they
are humans. Since there can be at least to a certain extent ambiguity in human
reason, it may seem that there is a primitive contradiction between
human reason and the holy texts. In fact, it is the necessity of
enriching human rights by revelation.
Participants in a cross-cultural dialogue, as Ken De Luca
puts, can agree on the right not to be subject to cruel and unusual punishment
while radically disagreeing upon what this means in practice — a committed
Muslim can argue that theft can justifiably be punished by amputation of the
right hand, whereas a Western liberal will want to label this an example of
cruel and unusual punishment. [18]
As human rights can be
enriched by culture and tradition according to communitarians, they can be
reinforced by religion. To simplify, religious human rights, here, mean human
rights according to the teachings of religion. Considering God as the wisest
being, there can not be any kind of contradiction between wisdom and the
sacred texts (religion 1). Having “religious human rights” is possible, because
there is no decisive reason to prevent us from referring to the sacred texts
themselves. Consider when the Prophet (p.b.u.h.) or Imam (a.s.) is alive.
Referring human rights to him, whether he agrees or disagrees with them, means
attributing human rights to religion. Although we are not in touch with the
prophet, the holy texts (religion 1) can be interpreted as the readings of the
sacred texts (religion 2). Hece, there is no difference between religion 1 and
religion 2 here, since both of them are hojiat (reliable based on Sharia).
From a theoretical point of view, having a system of Islamic human rights would be possible in the sense that a system of human rights can be established which at least resorts to Islamic presumptions. While applying the intra-religious propositions on human rights, this system must not contradict the mandatory requirements of religion. There is no general argument preventing us from referring to intra-religious evidence. Meanwhile, the necessity of reference to religion itself would not mean that whatever question raised by the human sciences and human rights can be answered by religion. Religion aims to guide human beings, while it may incidentally address other issues as well. The scope of such an address can be identified through reference to the inside of religion.[19]
Different
Speaking about
“religion” and “Islam”, it is necessary to specify and delimit their meanings,
since some readings might not confirm the enriching of human rights. As mentioned
before, by religion (and Islam) here, it is meant the interpretation of the
holy texts (religion 2), not the sacred texts themselves (religion 1) or the
behavior of believers (religion 3). According to Bassam Tibi, cultural Islam –
as a kind of Islam 3 - vs. political Islam is just a way of life.[20]
In Islam, there are at
least two major readings: minimalist and maximalist. The first reading views
religion as the relationship between man and God. Accordingly, fiqh
(jurisprudence) dedicates attention to private sphere; since social and
political holy texts (the Quran and traditions) are confined in specific time
and space. Whereas minimalists stress meta-textual reasoning, i.e.
philosophical and theological ones, maximalists concentrate on textual reasoning,
i.e. the sacred texts. On the contrary, maximalists hold that every case has a
religious, fiqhi, injunction.
As Michael Perry has noted, non-religious and secular
interpretations of human rights lack clarity, though this does not mean that
all religious readings of human rights are crystal clear.[21]
In his opinion, a secular reading of human rights is impossible. According to
his viewpoint, the concept of human dignity is basically approved by all
religions and philosophies, but it is only religion which can answer the
question why we should love others and respect their rights. It is the holy
Bible that defines our relations with our brothers, sisters, and neighbors in
detail. Someone like Camus may claim that he loves other people without any
religious sense. But the question is: on what basis? Are human morality and
emotions, precise and unchangeable through time?[22]
“Confluence
theory” chooses a middle way between maximalism and minimalism. This theory,
instead of stressing textual or meta-textual reasoning, believes in the
confluence of the two types of reasoning. Accordingly, fiqh play an important
role in social and political affairs, though, it does not have a commandment
for every case. I have applied this theory to the distribution of power[23] and human
rights.[24] In
any case, human rights can be enriched by religion based on maximalism or
confluence theory, however, minimalism (because of the minimal role of fiqh)
might not accept the enrichment of human rights. In brief, the guidelines of
confluence theory include: belief in human experience and reason more vast than
that in Shiite fiqh, considering modern methodologies like hermeneutics and
discourse analysis, the authenticity of political fiqh (despite minimalists),
and the non-necessity of Islamizing every social issue.[25]
Thin
and Thick Human Rights Bases
If one subjects the expression “human rights” to semantic
analysis, Soroush holds that the result would be the discovery of rights which a
human being enjoys by the mere virtue of his/her humanity and not because he
has adheres to a specific religion or because he obeys the orders of God.
Undoubtedly, here the conventional sense of right is meant and not its real
sense (or the objective and external reality or even a conception truly
corresponding to reality). Right in the conventional sense, means a permission,
a transitive right (which may be invoked against others), and entitlement.[26]
By introducing religion into the discussion on human rights, rights
transform into duties, and thus the main objective of the discussion
becomes irrelevant.
Covenant, as the main base of thin human rights, has been developed
by philosophers like Hobbes, Locke,
The other alternative for thin human rights might be the Golden Rule, i.e. “fairness principle”. Human rights per se should be universal, though the Declaration of Human Rights, like religions, is monistic. Accordingly, the unique foundation for human rights, not free from space and time, is fairness.[31] But we should consider that there is one exception: a fundamentalist, for example, does with others what he/she expects to be done with him/her, even when it is regarded anti human/humantarian rights. Moreover, human rights based on the Golden Rule might be too thin, since there is no way forward except though adopting what the partners have in common.
The thick human rights foundation,
here, is the necessity of reference to the holy texts; since it is not
impossible on one hand that this is the basis of rights, and it is a necessity
for believers on the other. However, it is assumed that since religious human
rights are idealistic, there is no way except to found thin human rights in the
relations of Islamic countries with the secular ones.
Conclusion
In the interaction between reason/revelation, textual/meta-textual reasoning, political philosophy/political fiqh (jurisprudence), “confluence theory” tries to seek a third way between minimalism and maximalism. This theory in the issue of human rights, like communitarianism, considers different contexts; and hence criticizes liberalism’s universal human rights. Liberals believe in universal human rights, however, communitarians consider divergent human rights in different contexts. According to this criterion, confluence theory inclines to the second one. It is worth emphasizing, according to “confluence theory”, there are some general and universal human rights. Despite postmodern relativism, human beings, ignoring their different beliefs and ways of life, have some universal rights in common. In short, confluence theory and liberalism are similar in stressing universal human rights, while the similarity of this theory with communitarianism is that it considers different human contexts, and hence different human rights based on dissimilar ideological and social contexts.
[1]. Shiite seminaries researcher and associate professor
in political science at Mofid University, Qom, Iran (www.s-haghighat.ir).
[2] . Michael Walzer, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and
Abroad, Notre-Dame:
[3] . Ibid, p x.
[4] . Sissela Bok, Common Values,
[5] . William O’Neill, “Thick or Thin?
Ethical Criticism”, CDSP 116, Fall 2006.
[6] . Benjamin Gregg, Thick Moralities, Thin Politics: Social Integration
across Communities of Belief,
[7] . Seyed Sadegh Haghighat, Tozi Qodrat (The Distribution
of Power in Shiite Political Thought) (in Persian),
[8] . Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue,
[9] . Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice, Which Rationality?,
[10] . Ibid, pp 1, 150, 228-229.
[11] . Ibid, pp 334-335, 389-390.
[12] . H. Tavassoli, Communitarians and the Critique of
Liberalism,
[13] . Oliver Leaman, “Rights and Religion: a False
Dichotomy”, Theoretical Foundations of Human Rights,
[14] . Charles Taylor, Philosophy and the Human
Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2,
[15] . W. Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture,
[16]. Ken De Luca,
“Perspectives on Political Science”, ????Summer 2003, Vol. 32 Issue 3, p184.
[17] . Robert Audi, The
[18]. Ken De Luca,
Ibid; see also: A. An-Naim, A., ‘Toward a Cross-Cultural Approach to Defining
International Standards of Human Rights: The Meaning of Cruel, Inhuman, or
Degrading Treatment or Punishment’, in Human Rights in Cross-Cultural
Perspectives: A Quest for Consensus, A. An-Naim, (ed.),
[19] . Seyed Sadegh Haghighat, "Theoretical
Foundations of Human Rights: A Comparison between Textual and Meta–textual
Reasoning", Theoretical Foundations of Human Rights,
[20] . Bassam Tibi, Islam between Culture and Politics,
[21] . Michael J.
Perry, The Idea of Human Rights : Four Inquiries,
[22] . Ibid, pp 11, 29, 16-19,
36.
[23] . Haghighat, Tozi Qodrat, Ibid.
[24] . Haghighat, "Theoretical Foundations of Human
Rights", ibid.
[25] . for application of “confluence theory” in Shiite
political thought, see my following article and books (at: s-haghighat.ir):
"Theoretical Foundations of Human Rights: A Comparison between Textual and
Meta–textual Reasoning", Theoretical Foundations of Human Rights,
Qom, Mofid University, 2005, Foundations, Goals and Principles of the
Foreign Policy of the Islamic State, Qom, Boostan– e–Ketab, (forthcoming,
in Persian), Distribution of Power in Shiite Political Thought, Tehran,
Hastinema, 2002 (in Persian), and Trans – national Responsibilities in the
Foreign Policy of the Islamic State, Tehran, Center for Strategic
Researches, 1997, (in Persian).
[28] . Imam Ali, Nahj Al- Balaghat, Sermon 21.
[30] . Mortaza Mottahari, Nezam Hoqoq Zan dar Islam,
[31] . M.M.Mojahedi, “Human Rights as Fairness: A Common Ground for integration
of Religious Obligations and Human Rights”, to be delivered in the 4th
Conference on Human Rights,
[32] . Mojtahed Shabestari, Ibid, p 238-242.
[33] . Seyed Sadegh Haghighat, "Jihad from Shiite Perspectives: Between Text
and Context", paper presented for the conference on "Scriptural
Hermeneutics", The Netherlands, 2006.